BREAKING NEWS

Monday, April 20, 2015

Moral Theory


(Ethical theory)
Ethical theory always needs attention, and with a special urgency today. The classical
canon – centered on virtue or consequences or duty – has opened the pathway to
sophisticated work in media ethics. However, a new generation of media ethics in
the multicultural and transnational mode requires that we retheorize existing theory
(see Christians, 2009). Rather than ethical theories rooted in rationalism that are
rule-ordered and gendered masculine, beliefs and worldviews should be made more
central in theory-making. Rather than a rule-based system, theory should empower
the imagination to give us moral discernment and an inside perspective on reality.
Even though we make an epistemologically acceptable move to more dynamic theory,
a crucial challenge is whether it answers the question, “Why should I be moral?”
This is a summary of the first primordial issue; what follows is an elaboration.

Presuppositional thinking
Mainstream ethical theory, grounded in rationalism, produces moral principles that
are unconditioned by circumstances. For ethical rationalists, the truth of all legitimate
claims about moral obligation can be settled by formally examining their logical structure.
Humans act against moral obligations only if they are willing to be irrational.
This kind of media ethics, rooted in classical moral philosophy, is unidimensional.
Autonomous moral agents are presumed to apply rules consistently and
self-consciously to every choice. Through rational processes, basic rules of morality
are created that everyone is obliged to follow and against which all actions can be
evaluated. In communication ethics, neutral principles operate by the conventions
of impartiality and formality. This is an ethics of moral reasoning that arranges
principles in hierarchical fashion and rigorously follows logic in coming to conclusions.
Journalism ethics that follows this approach, therefore, is based on standards
and doctrines that guide professional practice. In mainstream professional ethics,
codes of ethics are the typical format.
Utilitarianism is a single consideration theory, for example. It does not simply
demand that we maximize general happiness, but renders irrelevant all other moral
imperatives that are in conflict with it. Moral reasoning is equivalent to calculating
the consequences for human happiness. Utilitarianism presumes there is one
domain that determines what we ought morally to do. The exactness of this onefactor
model is appealing, but gains its validity by leaving out whatever cannot be
calculated. Kant is another example. He assimilated ethics into logic. Moral laws to
be universally applicable must be free from inner contradiction. Through the mental
calculus of willing an action to be universalized, imperatives emerge unconditioned
by circumstances. Moral absolutes are identified in the same rational way
that syllogisms are identified as valid or invalid.
A new generation of media ethics that is both intercultural and international
needs to go beyond one-dimensional models by incorporating presuppositions
into its theories. Human beings are committed to presuppositions inescapably. All
human knowledge must take something as given. A faith commitment is the condition
through which human cognition universally is intelligible. Theories of morality
do not arise from an objectivist rationalism, but from our fundamental beliefs
about the world. Worldviews are the gyroscope around which our thinking and
experience revolve. They are the home of our ultimate commitments at the core of
our being. Worldviews give meaning to our consciousness. They represent a set of
basic beliefs about human destiny. Presuppositions are therefore sine qua non in
rethinking moral theory

Why be moral?
Even if we broaden the boundaries of our moral theory to include the presuppositional,
does this retheorizing answer the question, “Why should I be moral?” When
theoretical models center on decision-makers who are accountable to a principle,
then why I should be moral is pertinent and answerable. However, when transnational
and intercultural beliefs and values are the target and beginning point, the
issue seems obscure and tenuous.
An inescapable contribution of classical theory is that they were serious about
addressing the question, “Why be moral?” The only presuppositional theory that
is acceptable is one that answers it also. The moral domain by its very character
entails the question. Like a magnetic force, the good compels me as a moral agent.
Should no such imperative exist, morality as a whole is incoherent. “Why should I
be moral?” is understood not as a prudential question (“Why is morality in my
interest?”), but as a question about justification: “Why should I accept the moral
demand as a demand upon me?” (cf. Hare, 2001).
The virtue ethics of Aristotle and Confucius both assumed that moral obligations
have authority from the community to which we belong. For Aristotle, the
city is like a parent; it has made us what we are. Membership in a community
reaches beyond our values and sentiments to engage our identity itself. To be true
to ourselves, we have to acknowledge the authority of the moral demand our community
instills into us.
Another alternative from the classics is to locate the authority of morality in
human nature, specifically in the organic human inclinations. In this perspective,
we can tell what is good for us by looking at what we are naturally inclined to act
upon. Doing the good benefits our human flourishing. For Jeremy Bentham, for
example, the chief good is satisfaction, and for all humans the source of their true
happiness is experiencing pleasure and avoiding pain.
For Kant, reason demands moral action. It is the nature of reason to will universal
law, and it demands this not only in theories of science, but in practical thinking
about what we do. Hence, we ought to base morality on reason. Reason is my
authority for acting morally.
If our motivation is only self-interest, psychoanalysis is needed, not morality. If I
decide to seek a Provost’s position because of my own career and without altruism,
then the moral domain has no validity. Forty-six million Americans are without health
insurance. Why should I care about health care reform if it means higher rates or
poorer quality for me? Politics or economics could explain my position – health care is
currently out of control and providing it more extensively hurts my small business. Or
politically, for the sake of our international reputation and attracting foreign investment,
our country should be able to match or exceed national health care anywhere in
the world.
Regarding the biological turn, why should I be held accountable if the moral
arena is subsumed by sociobiology or neuroscience? James Q. Wilson’s The Moral
Sense (1993) faces the critique that morality and sense perception are two different
domains. Morality is not like other human arenas, in this case, perception. I am
reading Charles Taylor’s The Secular Age and too preoccupied with it to lay it
down. I feel a moral compulsion to attend a university workshop on Palestinian
refugee camps, but decide in this instance to keep reading. But, I have no choice
regarding perception. I’m at my desk and the desk exists. The moral sense is inescapable,
but where is the moral demand in it?
For those of us committed to ethics, we insist on moral obligations as crucial,
over the long term, to human action. It is obvious in family life that self interest,
politics and economics do not exhaust our motivations. Regarding the environment,
a vocabulary of moral obligation is taking shape that will help ensure social
and cultural change. However, psychoanalytic, economic, and political explanations
are so powerful that the moral domain is typically rendered impotent. Once
again the urgent question – will a new generation of presuppositional theory be
able to answer convincingly, “What should I be moral?” To be intellectually legitimate,
resolving this issue is essential as media ethics theory is retheorized.[1]



[1] Clifford G. Christians, The Handbook of Global Communication and Media Ethics p1-4




Share this:

Post a Comment

Contact Form

Name

Email *

Message *

 
Back To Top
Distributed By Blogger Templates | Designed By OddThemes